"You can do anything you want so long as you don't bump
elbows with somebody else."
-- Virginia
Rohrbacher (1925-2000), c. 1965
The Bumping Elbows Rule (above) is a useful starting point
for discussing the concept of freedom. Consider that The Rule has two parts: 1) “You can
do anything you want”; and, 2) “so long as you don’t bump elbows with somebody
else.” Keep in mind during this
discussion that The Rule is more about what one *can* do rather than what one
*cannot* do.
The first part, “You can do anything you want,” relates to
our freedoms, which should be, generally speaking, open ended, except for when
we infringe on the rights and freedoms of others, which is what the second part
is all about. “So long as you don’t bump
elbows with somebody else” means so long as you do not create conflict with
someone else (see The Conflict Avoidance Axiom).
“Bumping elbows“ has a negative connotation in this context
meaning to bother somebody else. If you
are at a movie theater or sports arena, for example, and are hogging the arm
rests, then you are “bumping elbows.” If
you are at a crowded restaurant and are spreading out your arms and legs in a
territorial manner invading other people’s personal spaces, then you are
“bumping elbows.” If you are throwing
trash out of your car window onto somebody else’s lawn, then you are “bumping
elbows.”
Bumping elbows is not “bumping elbows” when both
participants agree to it (see Conflict Avoidance "One Off"). An example of when bumping elbows would be
acceptable is when both parties agree to bump elbows instead of shaking hands
because they agree that bumping elbows is a more sanitary method of
greeting. Since other layers of
consideration are also possible (see The Conflict Avoidance Axiom),
in order to avoid convoluted reasoning, “bumping elbows” is defined in the
instant discussion as having a negative connotation.
The Bumping Elbows Rule can be rephrased as a logical
statement:
IF you don’t
bump elbows with somebody else,
THEN you can
do anything you want.
An example of the above would be
if you want to read “The Adventures of Huckleberry Finn.” With the following assignments, The Bumping
Elbows Rule can be represented with symbolic logic:
A = You bump elbows with somebody else
¬A = You don’t
bump elbows with somebody else
B = You can do anything you want
¬B = You can’t
do anything you want
The ¬ symbol means “not.” Now, here is the symbolic logic for The Rule:
IF ¬A THEN B
The Rule can easily be manipulated
with logical operators. Modus pollens is
a logical operator that just restates the obvious. In purely symbolic terms, modus pollens looks
like this:
P → Q
P
∴Q
The → symbol means “then,” “implies that,” or “leads to.” The ∴ symbol means “therefore,” “yields,” or “proves.” The above logical sequence consists of three statements: 1) P → Q; 2) P; and, 3) ∴Q. “P” and “Q” can be any statements.
This is what modus pollens looks
like when applied to The Bumping Elbows Rule:
¬A → B
¬A
∴B
Reverting back to the original
phrases, modus pollens for The Rule becomes:
IF you don’t
bump elbows with somebody else,
THEN you can
do anything you want.
You don’t bump
elbows with somebody else.
Therefore, you
can do anything you want.
Modus tollens is a logical
operator that considers another possibility.
In purely symbolic notation, it goes like this:
P → Q
¬Q
∴¬P
When applied to The Rule, modus
tollens symbolically looks like this:
¬A → B
¬B
∴A
Reverting back to the original
phrases, modus tollens for The Rule becomes:
IF you don’t
bump elbows with somebody else,
THEN you can
do anything you want.
You can’t do
anything you want.
Therefore, you
bump elbows with somebody else.
A possible explanation for the
above sequence might be that you can’t do anything you want because you are in
prison, and the reason that you are in prison is that you “bumped elbows” with
somebody else.
The Rule can also be manipulated
with two false arguments. These false
arguments are useful to know because they help to determine when somebody is
trying to obtain incorrect conclusions to an argument.
“Affirming the consequent” is an example of a false
argument. In purely symbolic terms, it
looks like this:
P →
Q
Q
∴P
The above conclusion is
false! (The red
color is intended to emphasize that the conclusion is false.) Although the following statements use the
non-standard symbols ¬∴ for “not therefore,” it more accurately represents affirming the consequent.
P → Q
Q
¬∴P
The above statements mean “if P
then Q”; “Q”; and, “not therefore P”.
The correct conclusion in the above statements is that P may be either
TRUE or FALSE. (The words “TRUE” and
“FALSE” are spelled in all capital letters in this discussion when they mean
true or false in the sense of symbolic logic.)
Here is affirming the consequent
as it applies symbolically to The Rule:
¬A → B
B
¬∴¬A
Here is affirming the consequent
in the original phrases:
IF you don’t
bump elbows with somebody else,
THEN you can
do anything you want.
You do
anything you want.
Not therefore,
you don’t bump elbows with somebody else.
An example of the above would be
an insane person who does things without any regard for anyone else. This insane person may or may not be “bumping
elbows” with other people at the time.
“Denying the antecedent” is another example of a false
argument. In pure symbolic logic,
denying the antecedent looks like this:
P → Q
¬P
¬∴¬Q
If P, then Q. Not P.
Not therefore, not Q. Here is
denying the antecedent as it applies symbolically to The Rule:
¬A → B
A
¬∴¬B
Here is denying the antecedent in
the original phrases:
IF you don’t
bump elbows with somebody else,
THEN you can
do anything you want.
You bump
elbows with somebody else.
Not therefore,
you can’t do anything you want.
An example of the above scenario
would be a criminal who has not been arrested, yet.
A truth table is a useful way of
summarizing the possibilities in logical statements.
Fig. A, Symbolic
Truth Table of Statement
|
Fig. A is a symbolic truth table for The Rule that takes
into account every possible scenario:
both A and B are TRUE; both A and B are FALSE; A is TRUE and B is FALSE;
and, A is FALSE and B is TRUE. Four
possible scenarios exist and each possible scenario forms a row in the truth
table. The row colored red, for example, is the scenario where A is FALSE, ¬A is TRUE, B
is FALSE, and ¬A → B is
FALSE. Notice, by the way, that this is
the only possible scenario where ¬A → B
is FALSE.
This truth table can also be shown with the original
phrases.
Fig. B, The Bumping
Elbows Rule Truth Table
|
Fig. B shows the truth table with the original phrases from The
Rule. The red
row is the scenario where the Bumping Elbows Rule is FALSE: “You don’t bump elbows with somebody else”
and “You can’t do anything you want.” An
example of this scenario is that you are being coerced by someone else while
minding your own business.
The Bumping Elbows Rule is a useful starting point for
discussing the concept of freedom.
Consider, for example, “having enough elbow room.” The reason one wants “enough elbow room” is
to be able to do what one wants without “bumping elbows” with somebody
else. Consider, for example, the freedom
to state one’s opinion. One should be
able to state any opinion whatsoever because stating an opinion is not “bumping
an elbow.” Consider, for example,
victimless crimes (no elbows were bumped).
There is no such thing as total freedom: even if you are an alpha ape, you still
can’t just do anything that you want because you could still be overcome by,
say, numerous chimpanzees. (You might
also be limited in your actions by Mrs. Alpha.)
The Bumping Elbows Rule has two parts: 1) “You can do anything you want”; and, 2)
“so long as you don’t bump elbows with somebody else.” This rule is more about what one *can* do
rather than what one *cannot* do.
Do not bump elbows.Freedoms are open ended,But for that one thing.
Suggested Comments:
Is it ok to elbow your way to the top?
No comments:
Post a Comment